Popular Posts

Thursday, January 30, 2020

Recognizing Preexisting Indigenous Creative Jurisprudence: Kidjo Angélique v. Akpovi H. Athanase

Recognizing Preexisting Indigenous Creative Jurisprudence: Kidjo Angélique v. Akpovi H. Athanase   


Recognizing Preexisting Indigenous Creative Jurisprudence
*{66 J. Copyright Soc’y USA 1 (2018-2019)}     

**Kidjo Angélique v. Akpovi H. Athanase        

Infringing indigenous creative works is an equal opportunity lassie faire adventure recently. It involves all creeds, color and geographical location including stakeholders from the indigenous communities. African cultural contents used specifically for cinematographic creations deserve a renegotiated platform. Nigeria, Ghana, and most African legal systems protect their proprietary rights in their fashion design, folklore and cultural creative works.[1] The Beninese court in this case held that the popular African musician Kidjo Angélique infringed  Akpovi H. Athanase intellectual works.[2] The court further asserted that the author of an a intellectual work owns exclusive incorporeal property right in the work and its title enforceable against all parties.[3] In Benin Republic a French speaking West African country, the court denied the popular ‘Angelique Kidjo’ public domain defense to infringe on the intellectual creation of Athanase Houévègnon Akpovi in the songs that was the subject matter of an intellectual property infringement lawsuit.[4] The court reasoned that the elements of folklore copied in the songs, Makou, Gnonnou kpassou and Dogbe were originally created by Akpovi even though the songs were derivatives of folklore.[5]
Unlike copyright jurisprudence of the developed Western economies that grant little copyright protection or none to fashion design and folklore, the indigenous traditional legal system grants comparative advantage to creative works of developing economies.[6] However, a lopsided contemporary IP regime enhances proprietary rights of developed economies without corresponding IP protection for the creative rights of developing nations.[7] There is an apparent jurisprudential tension between the African and Western system on the issues of IP protection of culture.[8] Therefore, within the context of folklore and fashion designs, the African creator deserves a fair economic value and compensatory system based on the general objectives of the Lockean IP rights as practiced under Nigerian and most African legal systems.[9]
John Locke’s theory of propertied efforts and reward further supports legal protection for African folklore and culture[10]. Locke’s theory has remained the leading justification for intellectual property law.[11] Locke believed that people have inalienable natural rights to life, liberty, and property. Locke’s “labor desert” theory would hold that a creative genius like Fred Jones or the renowned African filmmaker, Tunde Kelani earned his inalienable right to profit from his arduous work as an imaginative inventor.[12] The Lockeans’ exertion of efforts in creativity seems to clash with the entire concept of folklore as a community production.[13] However, analyzing the Lockeans’ property-labor concept critically reveals that a community exerts significant efforts in preserving and innovating folklore to transmit it in its present form from one generation to the other.[14]
The labor and efforts exerted by the community equates to the Lockean bonafide of private property ownership rights.[15] Therefore, Folklore epitomizes the “purest” form of Lockeans’ “private” ownership of property and creativity.[16] Folklore is “pure” because unlike Locke’s creativity or productions, which inured from the labor or effort of the creator and exclusively owned by the private creator.[17] Folklore created from communal labor and efforts belong to all. It shades the monopolistic values of a Lockean creation.[18] Folklore is communal property freely accessible to the community and has utilitarian values.[19]  To update and refine Lockean IP rights for traditional indigenous and nonindigenous people, it would be necessary to extend his hypothesis to communal preservations of cultural creative expressions.[20]








* Samuel Samiai Andrews, SJD. “Reforming Copyright for A Developing Africa{66 J. Copyright Soc’y USA 1 (2018-2019)}
** Herve ́ G. Adoukonou.
[1] See Hervé G. Adoukonou, Recent Jurisprudence in Benin: Copyright-Authorship of the Work- Pre-existence- Plagiarism-Penalties, 36 Copyright Bulletin 58 (202); see also Paul Kuruk, African Customary Law and Protection of Folklore, 36 Copyright Bull. 5-35 (2002).
[2] Adoukonou, supra note 1.
[3] Id.
[4] See M. Stuart Madden, Myth, Folklore, and Ancient Ethics, 37 Cumb. L. Rev. 43 (2006).
[5] Adoukonou, supra note 1.
[6] See Jerome H. Reichmann, Universal Minimum Standards of Intellectual Property under the TRIPs Components of the WTO Agreement in Intellectual Property And International Trade 21, 22-23 (Carlos M. Correa & Abdulqawi A. Yusef, eds., 1998) (furthering the debate that the competitive nature of traditional industrial products
[7] See Paul Kuruk, Protecting Folklore under Modern Intellectual Property Regimes: A Reappraisal of the Tensions Between Individual and Communal Rights in Africa and the United States, 48 Am. U. L. Rev. 769-843 (1999).
[8] See Paul Kuruk, African Customary Law and Protection of Folklore, 36 Copyright Bulletin 5-35 (2002).
[9] See Paul Kuruk, The Role of Customary Law Under Sui Generis Framework of Intellectual Property Rights in Traditional and Indigenous Knowledge, 17 Ind. Int’l & Comp. L. Rev. 67 (2007) (describing the preexisting traditional jurisprudence under customary law to protect indigenous intangible creations in most African communities); see also Offrey v Ola & Ors Hos/23/68 (1969) (Nigeria) holding, supports the ‘sweat of the brow’ copyright ownership doctrine, which emphasizes the effort that a creator exerts in his or her creative work as the basis of authorial rights.
[10] See Robert P.  Merges, Locke for the Masses: Property Rights and the Products of Collective Creativity, 36 Hofstra L. Rev. 1179-90 (2008) (discussing the significance of recognizing political representatives of a traditional community as owners of communal rights in creative works).
[11] Id.
[12] See John Locke, Two Treatise Of Government (Peter Laslett ed., Cambridge Univ. Press, 1988) (1690) ; see also John Locke, The Second Treatise Of Government In Two Treatises Of Government, supra, § 25 ; see e.g. Diane L. Zimmerman, Information as Speech, Information as Goods: Some Thoughts on Marketplaces and the Bill of Rights, 33 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 665, 690-703 (1992); Tunde Kelani is the Nigerian International and award winning filmmaker whose cinematic works are primarily influenced and interpretative of Nigerian traditional cultures; see e.g. Olushola Adenugba,  Aesthetics in the Nigerian Film Industry: A Study of the Directorial Styles and Concepts of Amaka Igwe-Isaac, Muyiwa Ademola and Tunde Kelani, FilminNaija, (July 25, 2007), http://filminnaija.blogspot.com/2007/07/aesthetics-in-nigerian-film-industrya.html; see generally, Akinwumi Adesokan, Tunde Kelani’s Nollywood: Aesthetic of Exhortation in Postcolonial Artist And Aesthetics (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2011).
[13] See Wendy J. Gordon, A Property Right in Self-Expressions: Equality and Individualism in the Natural Law of Intellectual Property, 102 Yale L. J. 1533-1609 (1993).
[14] See Edwin C. Hettinger, Justifying Property, 18 Philosophy & Public Affairs 31, 36-45 (1989).
[15] See Benjamin G. Damstedt,  Limiting Locke: A Natural Law Justification for the Fair Use Doctrine, 112 Yale L.J. 1179-1221 (2003).
[16] Id.
[17] Gordon, supra, note 10.
[18] See Brian Cwik, Labor as the Basis for Intellectual Property Rights in Ethical Theory And Moral Practice, 7 Special Issue: BSET-Conference 681-695 (2014).
[19] See American Folklore Society, Recommendations to WIPO Intergovernmental Committee on Intellectual Property and Genetic Resources, Traditional Knowledge, and Folklore, 117 J. Am. Folklore 296, 297-98 (2004).
[20] American Folklore Society, supra note 16  (defining non-indigenous peoples as a group who have developed significant traditional knowledge and folklore over the course of generations in locations different from their historical places of origin); see also Bernard R. Boxill, A Lockean Argument for Black Reparations, 7 J. Ethics 63-91 (2003).